Volume 6 (2015) Issue 1
Forms
and Functions of Reflexive Structures in German
Katrin
Ziegler (Macerata / Italy)
Abstract
(English)
Morpho-syntactic
descriptions of reflexivisation processes
in German are usually based on a grammatical approach that considers
specific elements in terms of categories (for example, as individual
words: nouns, verbs or adjectives) without considering the variable
paradigmatic and syntagmatic relations of interdependence which link
the clause elements. This article, in contrast, adopts a functional
approach to the analysis of reflexive structures, in order to provide
an in-depth study of clauses as nexuses of grammatical relations. In
doing so, it provides a comprehensive description of the various
constructions containing German reflexive pronoun sich,
and attempts to provide systematic summaries of the complex sets of
forms and functions.
Key
words: reflexivisation processes, functional approach, clauses as
nexuses of grammatical relations
Abstract
(Italian)
Dietro
le descrizioni morfosintattiche dei processi di riflessivizzazione in
tedesco sta solitamente una prospettiva grammaticale che osserva i
singoli elementi dal punto di vista categoriale (per es., come
singole parole: sostantivi, verbi, aggettivi), non considerando
invece i mutevoli rapporti di interdipendenza paradigmatica e
sintagmatica che correlano gli elementi proposizionali.
Nel lavoro presente, invece, si procede ad un’analisi delle strutture riflessive adottando un punto di vista funzionale sotto il quale si esaminano le proposizioni in un modo complessivo e cioè come nessi di relazioni grammaticali. In questo modo è possibile fornire una descrizione unitaria di tutte le costruzioni marcate dalla presenza di sich e tentare sistemazioni organiche degli insiemi complessi di forme e funzioni.
Nel lavoro presente, invece, si procede ad un’analisi delle strutture riflessive adottando un punto di vista funzionale sotto il quale si esaminano le proposizioni in un modo complessivo e cioè come nessi di relazioni grammaticali. In questo modo è possibile fornire una descrizione unitaria di tutte le costruzioni marcate dalla presenza di sich e tentare sistemazioni organiche degli insiemi complessi di forme e funzioni.
Parole
chiave: processo di riflessivizzazione, interdipendenza paradigmatica
e sintagmatica, relazioni grammaticali
Introduction
Drawing
on a functional syntactic theory, this article examines reflexive
structures in the German language with a view to offering a
classification of such structures and a reflection on some of the
more challenging aspects inherent to the classification task. Despite
the existence of a vast bibliography on the topic, no experimental
tools have yet been developed to perform a comprehensive survey of
the complex set of forms and functions featuring the reflexive
pronoun sich, for the purposes of properly considering their
dissimilarities and any potential similarities in their features.
As
in the case of other languages, traditional studies of German grammar
tend to approach constructions involving the reflexive sich by
first considering the verbs with which it occurs (cf. Section 2). As
such, reference, for example, is made to ‘properly reflexive’
verbs and ‘inherently reflexive’ verbs. The limitations of this
approach are clear, however, if we consider that a single verb can
occur in a variety of structures and that, as such, these structures
are not necessarily linked to the lexical properties of their
individual elements. The verb class approach also fails to elucidate
the structural relationships among the different constructions in
which sich occurs.
This
article aims to perform a comprehensive overview of clause
structures. To this end, it draws on Relational Grammar (RG)1,
a framework which also provides the formal tools used in this study,
favoured because they are both easy to apply and effective in
highlighting the relevant issues.2
In line with this approach, this study does not focus exclusively on
individual words (nouns, verbs, adjectives) but rather includes
descriptions of interdependencies and syntactic correlations, from
both syntagmatic and paradigmatic perspectives. As such, clauses are
considered as nexuses of grammatical relations.
2 Status Quaestionis
In
German linguistic studies, ‘reflexive’ verbs are traditionally
classified according to the following categories.3
2.1
Categories of Reflexive Verbs
2.1.1
Verbs Used Reflexively
The
first category refers to ‘properly reflexive verbs’, the direct
or indirect object of which may either be reflexive or any other noun
or nominal group. The reflexive pronoun is the direct object (in the
case of the accusative) in example (1a), and the indirect object (in
the case of the dative) in example (1b):
(1a)
Die
Frau wäscht sich morgens sorgfältig.
[The
woman washes thoroughly in the morning.]
(1b)
Die
Studenten erzählen sich die letzten Neuigkeiten.
[The
students tell each other the latest news.]
While
the reflexive pronoun in construction (1b) is the argument of the
verb and, as such, necessarily part of the phrasal structure, the
reflexive in sentence (1c) is a ‘free dative’ (an optional
constituent):
(1c)
Meine Freundin kauft sich ein neues Auto.
[My
friend buys herself a new car.]
2.1.2
Inherently Reflexive Verbs
The
so-called lexicalization of the reflexive occurs both in clauses with
verbs that are entirely intransitive (sich) ängstigen (2a)
and in (anticausative) clauses that have a transitive counterpart
(sich) öffnen (2b):
(2a)
Meine Katze ängstigt sich sehr bei Gewitter.
[My
cat is very frightened of thunder storms.]
(2b)
Die Tür öffnet sich leicht mit einem Schlüssel.
[The
door opens easily with a key.]
2.1.3
Reflexive Forms with a Passive
Meaning
Reflexive
forms with a passive meaning feature the reflexive pronoun sich
in combination with intransitive verbs (3a) or verbs that are
considered detransitivized (3b):
(3a)
Es arbeitet sich gut in der Bibliothek.
[One
works well in the library.]
(3b)
Das Buch liest sich gut.
[The
book reads well.]
The
impersonal construction (3a) necessarily requires the inclusion of
the pronoun es which functions as the formal subject. An
adverbial modifier - represented in the above examples by the adverb
gut - is required in both the personal and impersonal
constructions; without a modifier, the sentence is incorrect.
2.1.4
Passive Reflexive
Constructions
of this kind (containing both passive and reflexive morphology)
involve verbs that occur in ‘properly’ reflexive structures (4a)
and those that are ‘inherently’ reflexive (4b). It should noted
that the passive reflexive is considered a rare variant of the
impersonal passive (Plank 1993), which, to date, has received little
attention. This
aspect will be discussed further in Section 4.
(4a)
Es wird sich morgens gewaschen; (Morgens wird sich gewaschen.)
[One
washes in the morning.]
(4b)
Es wird sich geängstigt bei Gewitter; (Bei Gewitter wird sich
geängstigt.)
[People
are frightened by the thunderstorm.]
Both
structures may contain the indefinite pronoun es; its
inclusion is, however, not obligatory under certain syntactic
conditions4.
2.2 Four Hypotheses Regarding the Properties of the Reflexive sich
Unlike
Italian, for example, which has two series of reflexive pronouns
referred to as ‘free’ and ‘clitic’, German has only one form
of reflexive pronouns. Reflexive pronouns in the first and second
persons are identical with personal pronouns; only in the third
person (singular and plural) is there a distinctive reflexive form,
sich, which has no number distinction and which syncretises
the accusative and dative cases.
In
the context of such a lack of morphological clarity, and using the
traditional classification method as a starting point, it is
difficult to discern whether any commonalities exist between the
various instances in which sich is used, and if so, what these
might be. The literature on this subject offers four hypotheses, two
of which (the first and last) contradict each other:
- The reflexive is considered a ‘full’ pronoun in all clauses in which it occurs. According to this perspective (Fagan 1992, Steinbach 2002, Bierwisch 2006), sich not only possesses (pro)nominal properties, it also retains argumental status - even in phrasal constructions in which it is not in paradigmatic commutation with the reflexive object. In such cases, it is assumed to have a ‘semantically empty’ theta-role and in the final analysis, the transitivity of all reflexive structures is affirmed. (cf. (1a) - (3b)).
- In clauses in which the reflexive is not in paradigmatic commutation with a non-reflexive direct object, it is compared with a formal object and therefore, while it retains precise syntactic functions, it does not necessarily have a semantic role (Pittner & Berman 2008). (cf. (2a) - (4b)).
- The reflexive is considered a syntactic marker of detransitivization and, as such, has pronominal properties which, in some structures, are relegated to the status of residuals (Plank 1986, Hundt 2001). (cf. (2a) – (4b)).
- The reflexive is considered an integral part of the verbal morphology (Grewendorf 1984, Everaert 1986, Cardinaletti 1999). Assuming that ‘inherent’ reflexive verbs have reflexive particles linked to them through lexical properties, it is not problematic to assign a ‘semantically empty’ status to the reflexives. The value of the commutation with non-reflexive direct objects is, however, lost. (cf. (2a) – (2b)).
Each
of the four hypotheses outlined above provides a different approach
to a series of related structural problems including, for example,
the issue of the transitivity or intransitivity of individual clauses
containing a reflexive pronoun (de Alencar & Kelling 2005).
Clearly, an evaluation of the transitive or intransitive nature of
constructions using sich will vary according to one’s
definition of reflexives as arguments or formal objects, syntactic
markers or integral parts of the verbal morphology.
2.3
A description of the Pronoun es
in Different Syntactic Contexts
The
challenge of defining the properties of the reflexive pronoun and,
therefore, determining the transitive or intransitive nature of
clauses using sich, also entails the problem of establishing a
coherent and consistent description of the indefinite pronoun es
in impersonal structures containing the reflexive pronoun. As
highlighted in the formal representation of constructions (3a), (4a)
and (4b), the es form in German grammar is traditionally
considered to fulfil the function of both formal subject (3) and
so-called place-holder (4a), (4b). This divergent description
of the use of the pronoun es in different syntactic contexts,
however, gives rise to an incoherent definition of the antecedent of
the reflexive pronoun in the structures in question, making it
difficult to engage in a uniform formalization of constructions with
reflexive morphology. In fact, traditional grammar definitions shed
little light on the relationship between the reflexive and passive or
between the reflexive and impersonal. As such, the few studies that
consider the passive reflexive in which reflexive and passive
morphologies converge present contradictory conclusions.
3 A Relational Perspective
The
descriptive problems referred to above relate to the perspective from
which the matter is approached, and change when that perspective
changes. The issue of whether or not to regard sich as a real
object, for example - a question obviously linked to whether or not
the related structures are considered to be transitive -, is cast in
a different light when considered from the perspective of RG. RG
starts from the assumption that
(…)
one cannot speak of sentences or even clauses as being transitive or
intransitive. This is a property of syntactic levels, reconstructed
as strata in relational networks. For example, it makes no sense to
speak of clauses as being transitive or intransitive because many
clauses are transitive in some strata and intransitive in others.
(Perlmutter 1983a: 151)
Principles
which apply to all structures clearly also apply to reflexive
structures. According to RG, clauses may be structured across several
syntactic levels, and functional commutations may occur between one
level and another. Thus, it follows that the same grammatical
relation (e.g. predicate, subject, direct object) may be borne
by different elements on separate levels (but not by two nominals in
a single stratum) (‘Stratal Uniqueness Law’ (Perlmutter 1983b:
92)).
3.1 Notions of RG Formalization
Fundamental
to the formal structure of RG is the concept that a nominal element
can relinquish its grammatical relation, either by acquiring a new
one (revaluation or removal) or by getting
syntactically 'lost'. These nominals, no longer able to engage in
morphosyntactic operations, are referred to as chômeur. To
clarify this point, the stratal diagram below5
presents the passive structure6
Das Bonbon wurde gegessen von dem Kind (The sweet has been
eaten by the child):
- Das Bonbonwurde gegessenvon dem Kind1Pchô2P1
Table
1: RG formalization of a structure containing a plain
personal passive
The
construction Das Bonbon wurde gegessen
von dem Kind (The sweet has been eaten
by the child) shows the 2→1 advancement from a transitive
initial stratum in which the verb essen ‘initializes’ a
subject (the person who eats) and a direct object (that which is
eaten). The nominal Das Bonbon acquires relation 1,
relinquishing its previous relation. The initial subject, das
Kind, has been demoted to the chômeur relation, which
means that it fails to control agreement with the verb, and occupies
an optional circumstantial role in the clause, introduced by
the preposition von.
3.2 The Unaccusative Hypothesis
It
will be clear by now that concepts of transitive and intransitive do
not apply to clausal structure as a whole, but rather to individual
syntactic strata7.
The concept of the intransitive form, meanwhile, can be further
broken down in RG, as demonstrated by Perlmutter (1978) in his
Unaccusative Hypothesis. This hypothesis proposes a
distinction between unaccusative and unergative
syntactic levels. According to this perspective, a structure, the
final subject of which also has the properties of a direct object -
for example the Italian sentence Lea è partita (Lea has left)
- constitutes an initial object (the initial level is regarded as
unaccusative). A structure such as Lea ha parlato (Lea
has spoken), on the other hand, in which the argument only bears
characteristics of a subject, must be considered monostratal and
unergative8.
3.3 Medium constructions
According
to definitions put forth by La Fauci (1988), constructions in which
the relations between the final subject and the direct object are in
commutative dependence - that is, paradigmatic (La Fauci 2007: 72) -
are considered ‘medium’. The characteristic trait of medium
constructions is that the final subject bears the direct object
relation at non-final levels of the clause. Medium
constructions are in opposition to so-called 'active’
constructions, in which the only possible dependence between the
relations of the subject and direct object is syntagmatic, and never
paradigmatic, and in which subjects do not therefore bear the object
relation at any syntactic level (La Fauci 2007: 72). The oppositions
between the active and medium constructions come under
the term diathesis. As well as passive structures, the medium
type also includes reflexive structures, which will be discussed
further in following paragraphs (cf. section 4.2).
3.4 The concept of Multi-Attachment
A
sub-set of structural types - formally characterized by the presence
of a syntactic level with ‘multi-attachment’ (henceforth MA) -
can be identified within the class of the medium constructions.
The
MA Hypothesis is a descriptive hypothesis that accounts for “certain
clauses with so-called ‘reflexive morphology’” (Perlmutter
1983a: 153). According to this theory, these clauses contain a
(non-final) nominal at some syntactic level that simultaneously bears
two or more grammatical relations - specifically subject and object
relations (La Fauci 1992: 45). MA does not occur at the final stratum
of the clause. As such, its resolution in a stratum subsequent to
that in which it is produced is indicated superficially by the
presence of the reflexive pronoun, causing the lower grammatical
relation to be cancelled (La Fauci 1992: 45).
3.4.1 Multi-attachment at Initial-P Level
Multi-attachment
can occur at the initial stratum of a clause, at the first level of
occurence of a predicate (initial-P). In the initial MA
structure, a single nominal element not only bears two grammatical
relations, it also serves two separate thematic roles (La Fauci 1992:
47)9.
As demonstrated in the RG formalization below, according to this
hypothesis, a classic reflexive structure such as La donna si
pettina10
(The woman combs her hair) involves the presence of a syntactic level
with MA at the first level of occurrence of the predicate11
(Table 2):
- La donnasi pettina1P1, 2P
Table
2: RG formalization of a reflexive structure with Multi-attachment at
the first level
Rosen
points out that MA
introduces
a specialized pronoun which takes over from the doubly attached
nominal one of its two relations - the lower one, normally and
perhaps universally. The specialized pronouns born under this
condition are reflexive pronouns. (Rosen 1988: 44)
As
shown in the above stratal diagram, the predicate pettinare
initializes both the subject (she who combs) and the object (she who
is combed). In the final syntactic stratum, however, the nominal
abandons the object relation, and only bears the subject relation.
3.4.2 Multi-attachment at Non-initial-P Level
In
cases in which MA appears in non-initial strata of the clause - at
levels subsequent to the first appearance of the predicate - “il MA
non è correlato col possesso da parte del nominale di
ruoli tematici distinti, poiché è l’effetto di un processo
squisitamente sintattico” [it is not linked with distinct thematic
roles of the nominal because the effect is that of a purely syntactic
process] (La Fauci 1992: 47).
In
structures involving MA in non-initial-P strata, the nominal acquires
a new grammatical relation at the advancement level while also
retaining the former relation unaltered (retroherent revaluation)
(La Fauci 1992: 48).12
In a structure such as Ugo si pente (Hugo repents), an
unaccusative or retroherent advancement occurs, as shown in the
following stratal diagram:
- Ugosi pente1P1, 2P2P
Table
3: RG formalization of a reflexive structure with MA in non-initial-P
strata
The
unaccusative verb structure does not have an initial subject, and the
2→1 advancement is referred to as retroherent
because the MA occurs at a syntactic level subsequent to the first.
Rosen
(cf. La Fauci 1992: 49) observes that structures with an unaccusative
valence can be further subdivided according to their (optional)
ability to initialize a subject, and to the retroherent and plain
modalities by which the advancement of the initial direct object to
the subject relation occurs.13
As
will be demonstrated later in this article (Section 4.2), it is our
belief that the classification of structures with MA, proposed by
Rosen for Italian, is also applicable to German. Caution must be
exercised in this regard, however, as it is difficult to accurately
establish the existence of a class of unaccusative verbs in this
language.
3.5 The notion of Dummy
Another
basic concept in RG is that the final level of a clause always
contains the grammatical subject relation (Final 1 Law
(Perlmutter 1983b: 100)) which may be present as a dummy.The
dummy can occur syntactically as, for example, in the English
clause It’s raining cats and dogs and the
French Il pleut des cordes, or can be silent, as
in the Italian Piove a catinelle14.
In German, the dummy is usually expressed syntactically as, for
example, in the clause Es regnet Bindfäden. As
demonstrated above, however, this element may be silent in some
structures and under certain syntactic conditions, as evident from a
comparison of the two constructions (4a) Es wird sich morgens
gewaschen and (4b) Morgens wird sich gewaschen.15
It
should be emphasised here (though it may already be clear), that RG
refutes the possibility of taking a generic approach to the notion of
subject: this notion must be considered specifically in
relation to each language, and broken down in accordance with the
significance of multiple syntactic levels. An analysis of syntagmatic
and paradigmatic relations performed by grammatical functions in the
various types of structures indicates that the empirical properties
attributed to the notion of initial subject differ from those
of the concept of final subject.
4 Syntactic Analysis of Structures with Reflexive Morphology in German
In
light of the premises outlined above and drawing on the
aforementioned tools, this section of the article will seek to
present a consistent formalization of reflexive morphological
structures in German. This formal description aims in particular to
highlight the syntactic conditions under which the passive and
reflexive morphologies converge in the passive reflexive structure
(4a) – (4b). As mentioned previously, the passive reflexive is
considered a (rare) variant of the impersonal passive and has been
subject to little analysis to date.
Researchers’
apparent lack of interest in this topic can be attributed primarily
to the fact that the structure is considered grammatically erroneous;
passive and reflexive morphologies are usually found in complementary
distribution and, as such, it is not strictly possible to transform a
clause with a reflexive verb into a passive construction16.
This
analysis also aims to provide a uniform, formal account of the
pronoun es in its various syntactic contexts. So, while in the
construction (3a) Es arbeitet sich gut in der Bibliothek, the
indefinite pronoun es is allotted the role of antecedent of
the reflexive as it is the formal subject, the presumed lack of a
syntactic subject in structures with the passive reflexive makes it
difficult to solve the problem of the antecedent in this kind of
clause. As mentioned above, the pronoun es does not have the
role of subject in this case.
What
syntactic element serves as the antecedent of sich, then, if
the reflexive does not have a subject within the same clause, in this
case a passive reflexive? One potential solution is to consider the
reflexive, in this case, as a simple detransitivization marker that
does not require a co-referring element (Plank 1993: 141-143).
Indeed,
in many grammatical frameworks17,
reflexivization is regarded as a mechanism of co-reference between
nouns and pronouns and, as such, the reflexive is considered on the
basis of its relation with other co-indexed elements within the same
clause or the same domain.
An
analytical approach of this kind, however, does not highlight the
interdependence between the reflexive and the passive, or between the
reflexive and the impersonal. The MA hypothesis, on the other hand,
enables the identification of shared features - for example the fact
that reflexive and passive constructions both have a final subject
which is (also) a direct object at some level of the structure (La
Fauci 1988: 15-27).
What
we wish to suggest here is that German reflexive structures can be
described in terms of the MA hypothesis; specifically, all relevant
reflexive constructions are characterized by a (non-final) syntactic
stratum with MA. Moreover, the constructions in question can be
further classified as structures with MA at initial-P level and
structures with MA at non- initial-P level.
4.1 Structures with MA at Initial-P Level
Let
us consider the hypothesis of an MA at the first level of appearance
of the predicate for properly reflexive structures, as in example
(1a):
- Die Frauwӓscht sich1P1, 2P
Table
5: RG
formalization of a structure with MA at initial-P level
The
nominal Die Frau, initialized due to the valence of waschen
as the subject and direct object, relinquishes the relation of object
at the final stratum and only bears the relation of subject. It
follows that the final stratum of the clause is intransitive, as it
only contains argument 1. As stated previously (La Fauci 1992: 47), a
structure with an initial MA implies both that a single nominal
element bears two distinct grammatical relations, and that it has two
thematic roles - as agent and patient. The resolution of the MA at
the final level of the structure causes the reflexive pronoun sich
to ‘inherit’ the lower grammatical relation (Rosen 1988: 44) from
the doubly initialized nominal. As such, its direct-object properties
are clearly accounted for, highlighted by the accusative case
marking.
In
example (1b), the grammatical relations also involve an indirect
object (Table 5), represented by number 3 in the stratal diagram,
which is typically marked in German by the dative case and which,
like the subject, participates in the syntactic process of production
and resolution of the MA:
- Die Studentenerzӓhlen sichdie letzten Neuigkeiten1Pchô1,2Pchô1,3P2
Table
5: RG formalization of a structure with MA at initial-P level
involving an indirect object
In
the case of properly reflexive structures involving an indirect
object relation18,
we propose that MA occurs at the first level of appearance of the
predicate. The verb erzählen initializes the nominal die
Studenten as subject and indirect object, and as agent and
beneficiary; the 3→2 advancement causes the initial 2 die
Neuigkeiten to become a chômeur, thus preventing it from
advancing further; and the MA 1, 2 is resolved in the final stratum
with the cancellation of the direct object relation. As such, the
structure is intransitive, as it only contains the subject relation.
The reflexive pronoun in this case inherits the lower relation, and
in fact has the properties of an indirect object, something which is
apparent, among other things, from the dative case marking.
Let
us now consider the hypothesis of an MA at initial-P level in the
case of the so-called passive reflexive construction (4a):
- EsProwird sich gewaschen1P21P1P1, 2P
Table
6: RG formalization of a structure with MA at initial-P level and
dummy 2→1 advancement
The
structure represented in the table includes a syntactic level with
initial MA due to the valence of the verb waschen, which
initialises a subject (he who washes) and a direct object (that which
is washed) confluent on the same element, ‘Pro’ (“unspecified
empathy focus” (Rosen 1988: 1986)). The resolution of the MA, then,
occurs in the following stratum of the configuration and
manifests in the appearance of the reflexive pronoun sich at
the final level of the construction.
The
dummy es which occurs at a non-initial level of the
syntactic scheme19
is initially attributed to relation 2, as RG specifies (‘Nuclear
Dummy Law’ (Perlmutter 1983b: 101)) that es can only bear
subject or direct object grammatical relations. Similarly, in
constructions involving the impersonal passive, a transitive level is
created in the stratum on which the dummy appears, thus enabling the
2→1 advancement of the dummy itself. This advancement is
responsible for the passive morphology in the passive reflexive.
Nominal
direct objects in conjunction with MA 1, 3 in the initial stratum, as
in the clause Es werden sich die Gesichter gewaschen, (They /
people wash their faces] (Table 7), can also be found in the passive
reflexive:
- EsProdie Gesichterwerden sich gewaschen1chôP21chôP1chôP1, 2chôP1, 32P
Table
7: RG formalization of a structure with MA 1,3 at initial-P level
and
dummy advancement 2→1
In
the initial stratum of the stratal diagram, Pro bears the 1, 3
relations simultaneously. The nominal die Gesichter is
allotted the relation of direct object, but loses this function with
the advancement of Pro to 1, 2 relation. The MA relation, in
the stratum subsequent to that in which it first occurs, is marked
superficially by the presence of sich.
The
dummy es, which bears the direct object relation, occurs at a
non-initial level of the syntactic representation. Similarly, in
constructions with an impersonal passive, a transitive level is
created in the stratum on which the dummy occurs, enabling the 2→1
advancement. This type of advancement is responsible for the passive
morphology in the passive reflexive.
4.2 Structures with MA at Non-Initial-P Level
We
will now analyse structures with MA at non-initial levels of the
clause, specifically at levels subsequent to the first appearance of
the predicate, with reference to example (1c), a so-called
‘anti-passive’ structure (Postal 1977):
- Meine Freundinkauft sichein neues Auto1Pchô1, 2Pchô1P2
Table
8: RG formalization of a structure with MA at non-initial-P level
Just
as in a passive construction, the initial level of an anti-passive
structure is transitive due to the valence of the verb kaufen,
which initializes the subject meine Freundin and the object
ein neues Auto. In anti-passive demotion, however,
there is no 2→1 advancement in the final stratum, as occurs in
passive promotion. Instead, the direct object is subject to a removal
process - as a result of a syntactic level in which one nominal bears
two grammatical relations - and becomes a chômeur. In both
anti-passive constructions - such as Meine Freundin kauft sich ein
neues Auto - and properly reflexive constructions (La Fauci 1992:
47) - such as Die Studenten erzählen sich die letzten
Neuigkeiten - German direct objects that have become chômeurs
are distinguished by the accusative case. This does, however, not
mean that they continue to fulfil the role of argument (in fact,
these structures cannot be passivized).
The
constructions (2a) - (2b), meanwhile, are both initially
unaccusative; they both contain final subjects that have the
properties of a direct object at some level of the syntactic stratal
diagram:
- Meine Katzeängstigt sich1P1, 2P2P
Table
9: RG formalization of a structure with MA at non-initial-P level
and
subsequent retroherent advancement
Let
us consider the hypothesis that structures of this kind contain
unaccusative verbs without initial subjects20;
in this case, the nominal Meine Katze bears relation 2 at the
initial level. The subsequent advancement is retroherent, and
therefore nominal 2 acquires relation 1 without relinquishing its
previous relation. The MA is then resolved according to the rules,
and the reflexive sich appears in the final stratum of the
clause.
Construction
(2b), the so-called anticausative construction, can be similarly
represented:
- Die Türöffnet sich1P1, 2P2P
Table
10: RG formalization of a structure with MA at non-initial-P level
and subsequent retroherent advancement
and subsequent retroherent advancement
We
propose that the German anticausative structure in example (2b)
contains a verb - (sich) öffnen - that can initialise either
the subject of a transitive clause Der Hausmeister öffnet die Tür
leicht mit einem Schlüssel (The caretaker opens the door easily
with a key) or a direct object in the transitive structure Die Tür
öffnet sich leicht mit einem Schlüssel (The door opens easily
with a key).
As
such, German anticausative structures can be represented stratally in
a manner similar to constructions containing so-called inherently
reflexive verbs, as the verb (sich) öffnen initializes the
nominal Die Tür in relation 2. The mode of advancement of the
initial object to subject relation is retroherent; an MA occurs in a
subsequent stratum of the configuration and is then resolved in the
final level of the clause.
There
are also causative verbs whose corresponding anticausatives do not
take sich in the intransitive clause, for example the verb
schmelzen (to melt). In the transitive construction Die
Sonne schmilzt das Eis (The sun melts the ice), the causative
verb initializes a subject; in the unaccusative structure Das Eis
schmilzt (The ice melts), meanwhile, the same anticausative verb
initializes a direct object with subsequent plain advancement. As
such, there is no reflexive marker.
The
MA Hypothesis in Relational Grammar facilitates a unitary account
both of German structures with atonic reflexive pronouns that have a
transitive counterpart, and of those that, at least in the modern
language, do not. Using RG, the various reflexive constructions can
be compared without reference to diachronic data, based on the
valence of their verbs and considering the modalities of syntactic
advancement - retroherent or plain. This also offers an explanation
as to why, in identical transitive constructions such as Die Sonne
schmilzt das Eis and Der Hausmeister öffnet die Tür,
the conditions for the presence of the reflexive morphology only
partially occur in the anticausative version.
Structures
(3a) – (3b) both feature a 2→1 advancement, either from an
initial transitive stratum or from a non-initial stratum of the
configuration (3a). Both constructions also feature retroherent
advancement:
- Das BuchProliest sichgut1ChôP…1, 2ChôP…21P…
Table
11: RG formalization of a structure containing a reflexive personal
passive
The
structure features 2→1 advancement from the initial transitive
stratum, in which the grammatical relation 1 is borne by Pro
because the verb lesen initializes a subject (the person who
reads) and a direct object (that which is read). The advancement is
retroherent. The nominal Das Buch acquires relation 1 without
relinquishing its previous relation. The MA produced in this way is
resolved by cancelling the lower grammatical relation (Blake 1990:
89). Pro becomes a chômeur, but serves the semantic
function of agent in the clause.
That
Pro becomes a chômeur is further confirmed by the fact
that this element cannot be added through an agent introduced by the
preposition von (by).21
Furthermore,
grammar rules relating to middle constructions in German require the
presence of an adverbial modifier at the final level of the clause.
Syntactic
descriptions proposed from an RG perspective in relation to
structures such as (3a) - the impersonal middle constructions - are
not entirely consistent (Rosen 1988: 98-122). As such, Perlmutter &
Postal start from the assumption that a construction containing an
Unspecified Human Subject (UHS), as in Es arbeitet sich gut
in der Bibliothek “involves a 2→1 advancement from a
transitive stratum” (Perlmutter & Postal 1984b: 137) and
should, thus, be considered, for all intents and purposes, a passive
structure. Likewise, “the advancement from 2→1 in reflexive
impersonal passives involves a 2-copy of the advancing nominal”
(Perlmutter & Postal 1984b: 137), meaning it contains an MA in a
non- initial-P syntactic stratum. The stratal diagram below
represents a structure containing a reflexive impersonal passive, as
proposed by Perlmuttter and Postal (1984b: 137):
- EsProarbeitet sich gutin der Bibliothek1chôPoblique1, 2chôPoblique21Poblique1Poblique
Table
12: RG formalization of a structure containing a reflexive impersonal
passive
Perlmutter
and Postal’s approach of assigning both a 2→1 advancement and a
retroherent MA to a UHS structure, such as the German impersonal
middle construction, also offers an explanation as to why
constructions of this kind are formed exclusively with unergative
verbs. Indeed, clauses such as *Es sinkt sich schnell im Meer
(One sinks quickly in the sea) or *Es kommt sich gut an mit dem
Zug (It’s easy to get there by train) do not exist in
German, as the verbs sinken and ankommen are
unaccusative verbs that have the phenomenal properties of an object.
Such structures would not only feature the 2→1 advancement of the
dummy from a transitive stratum, but also the unaccusative
advancement of the initial object to subject relation as in the table
below (Table 13):
- *EsProsinkt sich gutim Meer1chôPoblique1, 2chôPoblique21Poblique1Poblique2Poblique
Table
13: RG formalization of a reflexive impersonal passive
containing
double advancement
Double
advancement is impossible, however, as it breaks the One-Advancement
Exclusiveness Law which does not allow more than one advancement
to subject relation in a clause (Rosen 1988: 104, Perlmutter &
Postal 1984a).
The
final example (4b) of a construction with a reflexive pronoun
features a variant of the so-called passive reflexive, as it
contains an unaccusative verb:22
- EsProwird sich geängstigt1P21P1P2, 1P2P
Table
14: RG formalization of a structure with MA at non-initial-P level
and
2→1 dummy advancement
In
the sentence Es wird sich geängstigt, the unaccusative verb
ängstigen initializes an object, resulting in the occurrence
of the MA in a non-initial-P stratum. Nominal 2 is subject to
retroherent advancement, and acquires relation 1 without
relinquishing its previous relation. The MA is thus resolved
according to the rules, and sich appears in the final stratum
of the clause.
Relation
2 is first allotted to dummy es, which appears in a
non-initial stratum of the syntactic representation. As with
constructions using the impersonal passive, a transitive level is
created in the entrance stratum of the dummy. This transitive level
enables the 2→1 advancement, responsible for the passive morphology
in the Reflexivpassiv, to occur.
5 The Functional Domain [+MA] in German
The
above taxonomy of constructions with reflexive pronouns in German
enables the grouping of constructions of different structural types
in the functional domain [+MA], thus providing a description of all
constructions in which sich appears and offering consistent
and uniform answers to the questions raised in Section 2 of this
article:
- With regard to the question of the transitivity or intransitivity of reflexive structures, according to RG, such properties do not relate to the clause structure as a whole; this opposition (bearing in mind the potential distinction between two types of intransitivity) relates to the syntactic configuration and, if this is multi-stratal, to each of its strata. As such, although reflexive constructions are all intransitive in the final stratum, they are nevertheless transitive at some levels of the syntactic configurations;
- With regard to the convergence of passive and reflexive morphology in the passive reflexive, this article argues that German reflexive structures should all be analysed as examples of MA. The resolution of the MA in a syntactic stratum subsequent to that in which it is produced is superficially marked by the reflexive pronoun. The reflexive pronoun sich is therefore a systematic signal of the resolution of the MA at the final level of the clause.
The
MA hypothesis offers an explanation regarding the co-existence of
passive and reflexive morphology in the passive reflexive: the
MA does not conflict with the 2→1 advancement responsible for
passivization, and the presence of a 2, meaning a direct object, is a
necessary condition for reflexivization. An area of intersection
exists between the passive and multi-attachment domains, centred
around transitive verbs. Unergatives that permit passive morphology
in impersonal structures are excluded from the reflexive morphosyntax
(that requires the presence of a 2, meaning a direct object), and
while unaccusatives are not entirely unrepresented, they are not
common because, despite being perfectly compatible with reflexive
morphosyntax, they conflict, in principle, with passive morphosyntax.
It therefore seems reasonable to define the passive reflexive as an
extension of the impersonal passive beyond intransitive structures,
on account of the element sich, which syntactically marks the
presence of an object.
References
Abraham,
W. (2005). Deutsche
Syntax im Sprachenvergleich.
Tübingen: Stauffenburg.
Agel,
V. (1997). Reflexiv-Passiv, das (im Deutschen) keines ist. In:
Dürscheidt, Ch. (Hrsg.) Sprache
im Fokus. Tübingen:
Niemeyer, 147-187.
Bierwisch,
M. (2006).
German
Reflexives
as Proper and Improper Arguments. In: Brandt, P. / Fuβ,
E. (Eds.).
Form,
Structure and Grammar: A Festschrift Presented to Günther Grewendorf
on Occasion of his 60th Birthday.
Berlin:
Akademie-Verlag, 15-35.
Blake,
B. (1990). Relational
Grammar. London:
Routledge.
Brinker,
K. (1969). Zum Problem der angeblich passivnahen
Reflexivkonstruktionen in der deutschen Sprache. In:
Muttersprache
79,
1-11.
Cardinaletti,
A. (1999). Pronouns in Germanic and Romance Languages: An Overview.
In: van Riemsdijk, H. (ed.). Clitics
in the Languages of Europe.
Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter, 33 81.
Davis,
W. / Rosen, C. (1988). Unions as Multi-Predicate Clauses. In:
Language
64,
52-88.
De
Alencar, F. / Kelling, C. (2005). Are Reflexive Constructions
Transitive or Intransitive? Evidence from German and Romance. In:
Butt, M. / Holloway King, T. (Eds.). Proceedings
of the LF605 Conference.
Dubinsky,
S. / Rosen, C. (1987). A
Bibliography on Relational Grammar through May 1987 with Selected
Titles on Lexical Functional Grammar.
Bloomington: Indiana University Linguistics Club.
Duden
(Ed.) (2005). Die
Grammatik.
Bd. 4. Mannheim:
Bibliografisches Institut.
Everaert,
M. (1986). The
Syntax of Reflexivation.
Dordrecht:
Foris.
Fagan,
S. (1992). The
Syntax and Semantics of Middle Constructions.
New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Grewendorf,
G. (1984). Reflexivierungsregeln im Deutschen. In: Deutsche
Sprache 12,
14 30.
Grewendorf,
G. (1989). Ergativity
in German. Dordrecht:
Foris.
Haider,
H. (1985). Von sein und nicht sein: Zur Grammatik des Pronomens sich.
In: Abraham, W. (Ed.). Erklärende
Syntax des Deutschen.
Tübingen: Stauffenberg-Verlag, 223 254.
Helbig,
G. (2004). Kleinere
Schriften zur Grammatik.
Sitta,
H. et al. (Eds.). München: Iudicium.
Helbig,
G. / Buscha, J. (1998). Deutsche
Grammatik. Leipzig:
Langenscheidt.
Hundt,
M. (2001). Formen und Funktionen des Reflexivpassivs im Deutschen.
In: Zeitschrift für
Deutsche Sprache
2/02,
124-166.
IDS
(Ed.): Das Institut für deutsche Sprache Mannheim.
www.ids-mannheim.de. (1.2.2010)
La
Fauci, N. (1988). Oggetti
e Soggetti nella Formazione della Morfosintassi romanza
Nuova Collana di Linguistica. Pisa: Giardini Editori.
La
Fauci, N. (1992). Capitoli di Morfosintassi siciliana antica.
Tassonomia dei costrutti medi e ausiliari perfettivi. In: A.A.V.V.
Studi
linguistici e filologici offerti a Girolamo Caracausi.
Palermo, 43-73.
La
Fauci, N. / Mirto, I. (2003). Fare,
Elementi di sintassi.
Pisa: Edizioni ETS.
La
Fauci, N. / Pieroni, S. (2007). Morfosintassi
latina-Punti di vista.
Pisa:
Edizioni ETS.
Perlmutter,
D. (1978). Impersonal Passives and the Unaccusative Hypothesis. In:
Proceedings
oft the 4th meeting oft the Berkeley Linguistics Society,
Berkeley, 157-189.
Perlmutter,
D. (1983a). Personal vs. Impersonal Constructions. In: Natural
Language and Linguistic Theory 1,
141-200.
Perlmutter,
D. (Ed.) (1983b). Studies
in Relational Grammar 1.
Chicago: University Press.
Perlmutter,
D. / Postal, P. (1984a). The
1-Advancement Exclusiveness Law. In: Perlmutter, D. / Rosen, C.
(Eds.). Studies
in Relational Grammar 2.
Chicago: University Press, 81-126.
Perlmutter,
D. / Postal, P. (1984b). Impersonal
Passives and some Relational Laws. In: Perlmutter, D. / Rosen, C.
(Eds.). Studies
in Relational Grammar 2.
Chicago: University Press, 126-170.
Pittner,
K. / Berman, J. (2008). Deutsche
Syntax. Tübingen:
Niemeyer.
Plank,
F. (1993). Peculiarities of Passives of Reflexives in German. In:
Studies in Language
17-1,
137-167.
Postal,
P. (1977). Antipassive in French. In: Lingvisticae
Investigationes 1,
333-375.
Primus,
B. (1999). Grammatische
Hierarchien. Studien
zur Theoretischen Linguistik. München:
Wilhelm Fink.
Rosen,
C. (1988). The
Relational Structure of
Reflexive Clauses. Evidence from Italian.
New York: Garland Publishing.
Rosen,
C. (1997). Auxiliation and Serialization: on Discerning the
Difference. In: Alsina, A. / Bresnan, J. / Sells, P. (Eds.). Complex
Predicates.
Stanford:
CLSI, 175-202.
Rosen,
C. (2012). Dal
giardino della sintassi.
Pisa: Edizioni ETS.
Schӓfer,
F. (2012). The passive of reflexive verbs and its implications for
theories of binding and case. In: Journal
of Comparative German Linguistics.
Vol. 15, issue 3. Dordrecht: Springer, 213-226.
Steinbach,
M. (2002). Middles in
German. Amsterdam:
Anton J. Benjamins.
Steinbach,
M. (2004). Unaccusatives
and Anticausatives in German. In:
A. Alexiadou, / Everaert, M. (Eds.). The
Unaccusativity Puzzle, Oxford
University Press, New York, 182-206.
Vater,
H. (1995). Zum Reflexiv-Passiv im Deutschen. In: Popp, H. (Ed.).
Deutsch als
Fremdsprache. An den Quellen eines Faches. München:
Iudicium, 185-192.
Author:
Katrin
Ziegler
Università
degli studi di Macerata
Corso
Cavour, 2
62100
Macerata / Italy
Email:
k.ziegler62@gmail.com
1
Cf.
Perlmutter (1983b), Perlmutter & Rosen (1984), Dubinsky &
Rosen (1987);
for later developments Rosen (1988, 1997, 2012), Davis & Rosen
(1988), La Fauci (1988), La Fauci & Mirto (2003).
2
It
should be noted that the theoretical framework of RG has not changed
over the course of the last 30 years. The grammatical model,
however, while only used by Italianists in relation to Romance
languages, has evolved in several ways and, as such, provides
solutions to many linguistic problems.
3
Terminology
for reflexive forms in German is rather unclear and ambiguous. This
article draws mainly on the definitions provided in Duden
(2005) and in the Deutsche
Grammatik
by Helbig & Buscha (1998).
4
This
term, translated by Fagan (1992: 45) as “place-holder [which] is
restricted to sentence-initial position in main declarative
clauses”, describes the specific behaviour of the indefinite
pronoun whose specific role in this case is to occupy the
first position in the syntactic structure. Es
can be omitted,
enabling the formulation of sentences such as Morgens
wird sich gewaschen instead
of Es wird sich
morgens gewaschen and
Bei Gewitter wird sich geängstigt instead
of Es wird sich
geängstigt bei Gewitter. The
syntactic condition for this omission is that the first position in
the clause must be held, if not by the subject, then by another
grammatical element such as an adverb or complement.
5
Stratal
diagrams are read from the bottom to the top; the initial stratum is
the lowest, the final stratum is the highest. Symbols The
numbers
1, 2, 3 indicate the grammatical relations of subject and object
(direct, indirect), respectively, and the abbreviation P
stands for Predicate.
(Further relations e.g. instrumentalis, locative or temporal are
referred to as oblique).
It
should be noted that the diagrams in this
article only
include the relevant facts and do not consider, for example, the
distinction between the auxiliary and predicative sectors.
6
RG
defines four passive forms that are universally valid, irrespective
of the great variety of ways the four types are used in different
languages (Perlmutter & Postal 1984b: 126-170):
-
The plain
personal passive
as in Das
Buch wurde oft gelesen (The
book has often been read).
-
The plain
impersonal passive
as in Es
wird hier gut getanzt
(One can dance well here).
-
The reflexive
impersonal passive as
in Hier
tanzt es sich gut (There
is good dancing here).
-
The reflexive
personal passive
as in Das
Buch liest sich gut (The
book reads well).
7
RG
defines the individual syntactic strata as follows (Perlmuttter &
Postal 1984a: 95), indicating the grammatical relations of subject
and object with the
the numbers 1 and 2,
respectively:
a.
a stratum is transitive if and only if it contains a 1 and a 2
b.
a stratum is intransitive if and only if it is not transitive
c.
a stratum is subjective if and only if it contains a 1
d.
a stratum is objective if and only if it contains a 2
e.
a stratum is unergative if and only if it is subjective and
intransitive
f.
a stratum is unaccusative if and only if it is objective and
intransitive
8The
properties and behaviour that typify unergative and unaccusative
verbs must be specified on a language-by-language basis. Such
properties range from the choice of the auxiliary in compound tenses
to the admissibility of certain constructions. In order to identify
the two unergative or unaccusative classes in Italian, for example,
a series of syntactic tests have been devised (Perlmutter 1978,
Rosen 1988) which are highly accurate and which have made it
possible to “grammaticalize” unaccusativity in Italian, which is
clearer than in other languages. The definition of tests appropriate
to German has proven more difficult, and this has resulted in a
semantic definition of unaccusativity being favoured (Steinbach
2004). This situation will be discussed further in Section 4.2.
9
It
should be noted
that this study exclusively relates to structures with a single
semantically active predicate sector and that, as
such, causative and other such structures are not taken into
account.
10
All
relevant studies to date have looked at Italian reflexives (Rosen
1988); as such, the examples used in this article relate to Italian.
11
Rosen
(ibid) deals with the Italian clitic reflexive ‘si’ and examines
the morphosyntactic differences between the various structures and
different syntactic levels in which it occurs. It should be noted
that from an RG perspective ‘si’ is considered as a ‘reflexive
marker’, “taken to reflect multiattachment” (Blake 1990: 72),
whereas the pronoun ‘se (stesso)’ “is treated like other
nominals and allotted appropriate initial stratum relations”
(Blake: ibid).
12
Rosen
states: “
[…] there exist two types of advancement, plain and retroherent.
In the [plain] advancement the advancee acquires a new relation and
relinquishes its former one. In a retroherent advancement, the
advancee acquires a new relation and retains its former relation
besides” (Rosen 1988: 22).
13
An
unaccusative verb such as pentire
(to repent) uses the retroherent modality for the advancement of the
initial object, but cannot take an initial subject: Ugo
si pente
(Hugo repents), *Lea
pente Ugo *
(Lea repents Hugo(, *Ugo
pente (Hugo
repents). An unaccusative verb such as riempire
(to fill), however, while using the retroherent modality in the same
way to advance the initial object in the structure, takes an initial
subject in some constructions: Ugo
riempie la bottiglia di vino
(Hugo fills the bottle with wine), la
bottiglia si riempie di vino
(The bottle is filled with wine), *la
bottiglia riempie di vino *(The
bottle fills with wine). By contrast, the verb arrivare
(to
arrive) never takes an initial subject and the modality to move on
the initial object is plain advancement: Ugo
arriva (Ugo
arrives), *Pia arriva Ugo *(Pia arrives Ugo), *Ugo
si arriva *(Hugo
arrives himself).
14
See
Perlmutter (1983b) and Rosen (1988) on the silent dummy in Italian.
15
As
already stated, in certain syntactic contexts, German traditional
grammar clearly identifies that the indefinite pronoun es
has two functions. It states that es
can
either be the formal subject or the place-holder. RG however, in the
grammatical contexts in question, only attributes one function to
this element, that of the dummy which syntactically maintains the
subject relation in the final level of the configuration.
16
It
should be emphasized that the
passive reflexive is a construction used diastratically and
diaphasically with growing frequency at the same rate as it is
integrated into standard
language.
17
As
Rosen states:
According to one classic transformational view (e. g. Lees and
Klima 1963), Reflexivization is a rule sensitive to coreference
between two nominals, among other conditions. But if the
Multiattachment Hypothesis is adopted together with the idea of
pronoun birth, the result is that the concept of coreference would
not figure at all in the conditioning on Reflexivization (Rosen
1988: 44).
18
This
article adopts La Fauci’s proposal regarding analogous romance
constructions (La Fauci 1988: 83-84), which assumes the presence of
an intermediate level with MA [1, 2] for the resolution of MA in
reflexive constructions with a direct object. One advantage of this
approach is that it explains why it is impossible to make these
structures passive. The assumption of an intermediate stratum, and
therefore of a 3→2 advancement,
“omogeneizza,
per effetto della risoluzione del seguente MA 1,2 sotto questo
rispetto proposizioni riflessive con MA 1,3 e proposizioni
riflessive con MA 1,2” [ harmonises reflexive clauses with
MA
1,3 and reflexive clauses with MA 1,2 leading to the resolution of
the MA 1,2 that follows] (La Fauci ibid:
83).
19
Es
can only occur in post-initial strata, otherwise it would defy the
‚Stratal Uniqueness Law‘.
20
The
diagnostics of German unaccusative structures is anything but
straightforward. Steinbach states that
“the
diagnostics for unaccusativity in German yield no clear evidence for
the claim that unaccusativity in German must be encoder (sic!) in
syntax […] unaccusative verbs differ from unergative verbs at
least in their semantics and selectional properties. Typical
unaccusative verbs select a semantic argument which has
proto-patient properties as opposed to typical unergative verbs,
which select a semantic argument with proto-agent properties”.
(Steinbach (2004: 182-183)
Semantically,
the verb ängstigen
with a reflexive marker describes an event that is not controlled by
its protagonist, expressing a state of being or feeling that does
not depend on the will of the person involved in the action. A verb
of this type can be considered unaccusative and can therefore
syntactically initialize an object, in this case the nominal meine
Katze.
It should be noted that in German, unlike in Italian, it is somewhat
difficult to base the distinction between classes of unaccusative or
unergative verbs on syntax. A
series of diagnostic tests exist to define the different properties
of the two sub-groups. For
example, unaccusative verbs cannot be found in impersonal passive
structures, nor can they be nominalized (Grewendorf 1989, Haider
1985, Primus
1999,
Abraham 2005).
21Rosen
observes that:
the
two varieties of Passive - plain and retroherent - differ not only
in their morphological concomitants, but also in the conditions that
govern their appropriateness. One clear fact is that the chômeur
of a Plain Passive can be either overt or unspecified (…) whereas
the chômeur of
a Retro Passive can never be overt […]. (Rosen 1988:86)
22
Passive
reflexive structures basically involve transitive verbs (as in Es
wird sich gewaschen)
or unaccusative verbs (as in Es
wird sich geängstigt).
The
passive
reflexive never occurs with unergative verbs (as in *Es
wird sich gut
gearbeitet).
An
examination of the corpora (Institut für deutsche Sprache, Hundt
2001, Vater 1995) suggests that the passive reflexive is rarely
constructed with unaccusative verbs. The few exceptions are not
entirely convincing, and the verbs involved seem to have previously
been transitive. (Fagan (1992: 237) for further information
regarding the transitive variants of inherently reflexive verbs in
German.)